(by Jonny)
A couple of weeks ago I posted about a
problem that occasionally surfaces in philosophy of cognition,
particularly embodied cognition. It's the problem of relativism. It's
a problem, in my eyes, because it's an unnecessary obstacle for
certain very intuitive ideas to become acceptable to many people,
it's a distraction. Though the notion an organism's experience of
the world is necessarily dependent on contingent sensorimotor
capacities is highly plausible, though the notion that the way the
world is largely relative to our particular bodily form, and that
form's contingent interaction with the world makes some immediate
sense, relativism is off-puttingly problematic.
Well I recently came across an example
of this sort of view in the form of Chemero's (1998) review of Andy
Clark's “Being There” (1997). Chemero, who otherwise positively
recommends Clark's embodied conclusions, complains of the author's
unwillingness to accept that his thesis implies a rejection of
“world-it-itself”, of “scientific realism”.
Andy Clark's "Being There" |
The precise reason remains a mystery to
me. Chemero seems sensible when he says,
“Since
there is no central executive in mobots with connectionist brains,
there
will be no detailed, action-neutral representation of the
world. In most cases, agents will
use the world as its own model.
”
(pg.3)
And it sensibly
follows from the central ideas of embodied cognition that,
“we
should expect creatures (including humans)
to be sensitive only to
those aspects of their environments that matter to the actions they
regularly undertake... The world represented by animals with much
different needs than humans will be much
different than the world
humans represent.”
(pp.5-6)
But it does not seem
to follow that there is no world “in and of itself” independent
of our perceptions. One of the issues seems to be Chemero's notion of
what realism exactly says. He writes that falsehood of
we must
reject “so-called "common-sense realism," in which the
world-in-itself is thought to correspond
to everyday human
categories.
” But it is ambiguous what he means by everyday human
categories. Perhaps, as I mentioned in my last post, we will have
reject the idea that the world is conveniently structured as our
thoughts are structured. The world as constituted by giraffes and
cactus and melons is a contingent, human perception of the world
based on human needs, but it does not imply that the existence of
giraffes is entirely relative. There is still something about
the giraffe that exists independent of an organism's contingent
situation. So perhaps we will reject a certain everyday realism, a
realism that takes the world to always conform to everyday human
categories, but this is a weak realism.
Though
Chemero is right to say that “physics and other
sciences depend
upon our language-using abilities” (pg.7), he is wrong to conclude
that science does not tell us something, in some form, about the real
independent properties of the universe.
Embodied cognition does not
entail, and should not imply, this sort of radical relativism.
How I feel when I start thinking about cognitive science and relativism. |
Chemero,
A (1998) A Stroll Through the Worlds of Animals
and
Humans:
Review of Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World
Together Again by Andy Clark.
Psyche,
4(14)
Clark,
A (1997) Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World
Together
Again. MIT Press:
Cambridge, Massachusetts
Agreed. I've just been reading Shapiro's 'Embodied Cognition', and he expresses similar concerns with several pioneering theorists who greatly overstate the 'relativistic' implications of embodiment. Just because my perceptions depend on the particular evolution of my perceptual apparatus, doesn't mean that the basic input data (to that apparatus) isn't the same regardless of my evolution. There's certainly some interesting work to be done (and being done) in evolutionary epistemology, but saying that creatures literally "make their own world" when they perceive just muddies the waters.
ReplyDeleteNow, talking metaphorically of the worlds that are made, probably in order to make an ethical or political (or otherwise normative) point is perhaps a different matter, but not one that directly concerns cognitive science. It's also true that traditional cognitive science has tended to overemphasise the isolation of the brain, but that's no reason to discard everything that it's achieved. Everyone needs to calm down a bit...